Peter F. Drucker:
Modern Prophets: Schumpeter and Keynes?
The two greatest economists of this century, Jospeh A. Shumpeter and John Maynard
Keynes, were born, only a few months apart, a hundred years ago: Schumpeter on
February 8, 1883, in a provincial Austrian town; Keynes on June 5, 1883, in Cambridge,
England. (And they died only four years apart - Schumpeter in Connecticut on January 8,
1950, Keynes in southern England on April 21, 1946.) The centenary of Keynes's birth is
being celebrated with a host of books, articles, conferences, adn speeches. If the
centenary of Schumpeter's birth were noticed at all, it would be in a small doctoral
seminar. And yet it is becoming increasingly clear that it is Schumpeter who will shape
the thinking and inform the questions on economic policy for the rest of this century, if
not for the next thirty or fifty years.
The two men were not antagonists. Both challenged longstanding assumptions. The
opponents of Keynes were the very "Austrians" Schumpeter himself had broken away
from as a student, the neoclassical economists of the Austrian School. And although
Schumpeter considered all of Keynes's answers wrong, or at least misleading, he was a
sympathetic critic. Indeed, it was Schumpeter who established Keynes in America. When
Keynes's masterpiece, The General Theory of Employment, Interest and Money, came
out in 1936, Schumpeter, by then the senior member of Harvard economics faculty, told
his students to read the book and told them also that Keynes's work had totally
superseded his own earlier writings on money.
Keynes, in turn, considered Schumpeter one of the few contemporary economists worthy
of his respect. In his lectures he again and again referred to the works Schumpeter had
published during World War I, and especially to Schumpeter's essay on Rechenpfennige
(that is, money of account) s the initial stimulus for his on thoughts on money. Keynes's
most successful policy initiative, the proposal that Britain and the United States finance
World War II by taxes rather than by borrowing, came directly out of Schumpeter's 1918
warning of the disastrous consequences of the debt financing of World War I.
Schumpeter and Keynes are often contrasted politically, with Schumpeter being portraye
as the "conservative" and Keynes the "radical." The opposite is more nearly right.
Politically Keynes's views were quite similar to what we now call "neoconservatice." His
theory had its origins in his passionate attachment to the free market and in his desire to
keep politicans and governments out of it. Schumpeter, by contrast, had serious doubts
about the free market. He thought that an "intelligent monopoly" - the American Bell
Telephone system, for instance - had a great deal to recommend itself. It could afford to
take the long view instead of being driven from transaction to transaction by short-term
expediency. His closest friend for many years was the most radical and most doctrinaire
of Europe's left-wing socialists, the Austrian Otto Bauer, who, though staunchly
anticommunist, was even more anticapitalist. And Schumpeter, although never even
close to being a socialist himself, served during 1919 as minister of finance in Austria's
only socialist government between the wars. Schumpeter always maintained that Marx
had been dead wrong in every one of his answers. But he still considered himself a son of
Marx and held him in greater esteem than any other economist. At least, so he argued,
Marx asked the right questions, and to Schumpeter questions were always more
important than answers.
The differences between Schumpeter and Keynes go much deeper than economic
theorems or political views. The two saw a different economic reality, were concerned
with different problems, and defined economics quite differently. These differences are
highly important to an understanding of today's economic world.
Keyned, for all that he broke with classical economics, operated entirely within its
framework. He was an heretic rather than an infidel. Economics, for Keynes, was the
www.peterdrucker.at 2
equilibrium economics of Ricardo's 1810 theories, which dominated the nineteenth
century. This economics deals with a closed system and a static one. Keynes's key
question was the same question the nineteenth-century economists had asked: "How can
one maintain an economy in balance and stasis?"
For Keynes, the main problems of econimics are the relationship between the "real
economy" of goods and services and the "symbol economy" of money and credit; the
relationship between individuals and businesses and the "macroeconomy" of the nationstate; and finally, whether production (that is, supply) or consumption (that is, demand)
provides the driving force of the economy. In this sense Keynes was in a direct line with
Ricardo, John Stuart Mill, the "Austrians," and Alfred Marshall. However much they
differed otherwise, most of these nineteenth-century economists, and that includes Marx,
had given the same answers to these questions: The "real economy" controls, and
money is only the "wil of things," the microeconomy of individuals and businesses
determines, and government can, at best, correct minor discrepancies and, at worst,
create dislocations; and supply controls, with demand a function of it.
Keynes asked the same questions that Ricardo, Mill, Marx, the "Austrians," and Marshall
had asked but, with unprecedented audacity, turned every one of the answers upside
down. In the Keynesian system, the "symbol economy" of money and credit are "real,"
and goods and services dependent on it and its shadows. The macroeconomy - the
economy of the nation-state - is everything, with individuals and firms having neither
power to influence, let alone to direct, the economy nor the ability to make effective
decisions counter to the forces of the macroeconomy. And economic phenomena, capital
formation, productivity, and employment are functions of demand.
By now we know, as Schumpeter knew fifty years ago, that every one of these Keynesian
answers is the wrong answer. At least they are valid only for special cases and within
fairly narrow ranges. Take, for instance, Keynes's key theorem: that monetary events -
government deficits, interest rates, credit volume, and volume of money in circulation -
determine demand and with it economic conditions. This assumes, as Keynes himself
stressed, that the turnover velocity of money is constant and not capable of being
changed over the short term by individuals or firms. Schumpeter pointed out fifty years
ago that all evidence negates this assumption. And indeed, whenever tried, Keynesian
economic policies, whether in the original Keynesian or in the modified Friedman version,
have been defeated by the microeconomy of business and individuals, unpredictably and
without warning, changing the turnover velocity of money almost overnight.
When the Keynesian prescriptions were initially tried - in the United States in the early
New Deal days - they seemed at first to work. But then, around 1935 or so, consumers
and businesses suddenly sharply reduced the trunover velocity of money within a few
short months, which aborted a recovery based on government deficit spending and
brought about a second collapse of the stock market in 1937. The best example,
however, is what happened in this country in 1981 and 1982. The Federal Reserve's
purposeful attempt to control the economy by controlling the money supply was largely
defeated by consumers and businesses who suddenly and most violently shifted deposits
from thrifts into money-market funds and from long-term investments into liquid assets -
that is, from low-velocity into high-velocity money - to the point where no one could
really tell anymore what the money supply is or even what the term means. Individuals
and businesses seeking to optimize their self-interest and guided by their perception of
economic reality will always find a way to beat the "system" - whether, as in the Soviet
bloc, through converting the entire economy into one gigantic black market or, as in the
United States in 1981 and 1982, through transforming the financial system overnight
despite laws, regulations, or econimists.
This does not mean that economics is likely to return to pre-Keynesian neoclassicism.
Keynes's critique of the neoclassic answers is as definitive as Schumpeter's critique of
Keynes. But because we now know that individuals can and will defeat the system, we
have lost the certainty which Keynes imposed on economics and wich has made the
www.peterdrucker.at 3
Keynesian system the lodestar of economic theory and economic policy for fifty years.
Both Friedman's monetarism and supply-side economics are desperate attempts to patch
up the Keynesian system of equilibrium economics. But it is unlikely that either can
restore the self-contained, self-confident equilibrium economics, let alone an economic
theory or an economic policy in which one factor, whether government spending, interest
rates, money supply, or tax cuts, controls the economy predictably and with nearcertainty.
That the Keynesian answer were not going to prove any more valid than the preKeynesian ones that they replaced was clear to Schumpeter from the beginning. But to
him this was much less important than that the Keynesian questions - the questions of
Keynes's predecessors as well - were not, Schumpeter thought, the important questions
at all. To him the basic fallacy was the very assumption that the healthy, the "normal,"
economy is an economy in static equilibrium. Schumpeter, from his student days on, held
that a modern economy is always in dynamic disequilibrium. Schumpeter's economy is
not a closed system like Newton's universe - or Keynes's macroeconomy. It is forever
growing and changing and is biological rather than mechanistic in nature. If Keynes was
a "heretic,"
Schumpeter was an "infidel."
Schumpeter was himself a student of the great men of Austrian economics and at a time
when Vienna was the world capital of economic theory. He held his teachers in lifelong
affection. But his doctoral dissertation - it became the earliest of his great books, The
Theory of Economic Development (which in its original German version came out in
1911, when Schumpeter was only twenty-eight years old) - starts out with the assertion
that the central problem of economics is not equilibrium but structural change. This then
led to Schumpeter's famous theorem of the innovator as the true subject of economics.
Classical economics considered innovation to be outside the system, as Keynes did, too.
Innovation belonged in the category of "outside catastrophies" like earthquakes, climate,
or war, which, everybody knew, have profound influence on the economy but are not
part of economics. Schumpeter insisted that, on the contrary, innovation - that is,
entrepeneurship that moves resources from old and obsolescent to new and more
productive employments - is the very essence of economics and most certainly of a
modern economy.
He derived this notion, as he was the first to admit, from Marx. But he used it to disprove
Marx. Schumpeter's Economic Development does what neither the classical economists
nor Marx nor Keynes was able to do: It makes profit fulfill an economic function. In the
economy of change and innovation, profit, in contrast to Marx and his theory, is not a
Mehrwert, a "surplus value" stolen from the workers. On the contrary, it is the only
source of jobs for workers and of labor income. The theory of economic development
shows that no one except the innovator makes a genuine "profit"; and the innovator's
profit is always quite short-lived. But innovation in Schumpeter's famous phrase is also
"creative destruction." It makes obsolete yesterday's capital equipment and capital
investment. The more an economy progresses, the more capital formation will it
therefore need. Thus what the classical economists - or the accountant or the stock
exchange - considers "profit" is a genuine cost, the cost of staying in business, the cost
of a future in which nothing is predictable except that today's profitable business will
become tomorrow's white elephant. Thus, capital formation and productivity are needed
to maintain the wealth-producing capacity of the economy and, above all, to maintain
today's jobs and to create tomnorrow's jobs.
Schumpeter's "innovator" with his "creative destruction" is the only theory so far to
explain why there is something we call "profit." The classical economists very well knew
that their theory did not give any rationale for profit. Indeed, in the equilibrium
economics of a closed economic system there is no place for profit, no justification for it,
no explanation of it. If profit is, however, a genuine cost, and especially if profit is the
only way to maintain jobs and to create new ones, then capitalism becomes again a
www.peterdrucker.at 4
moral system.
Morality and profits: The classical economists had pointed out that profit is needed as the
incentive for the risk taker. But is this not really a bribe and thus impossible to justify
morally? This dilemma had driven the most brilliant of the nineteenth-century
economists, John Stuart Mill, to embrace socialism in his later years. It had made it easy
for Marx to fuse dispassionate analysis of the "system" with the moral revulsion of an Old
Testament prophet against the exploiters. The weakness on moral grounds of the profit
incentive enabled Marx at once to condemn the capitalist as wicked and imoral and
assert "scientifically" that he serves no function and that his speedy demise is
"inevitable." As soon, however, as one shifts from the axiom of an unchanging, selfcontained, closed economy to Schumpeter's dynamic, growing, moving, changing
economy, what is called profit is on longer immoral. It becomes a moral imperative.
Indeed, the question then is no longer the question that agitated the classicists and still
agitated Keynes: How can the economy be structured to minimize the bribe of the
functionless surplus called profit that has to be handed over to the capitalist to keep the
economy going? The question in Schumpeter's economics is always, Is there sufficient
profit? Is there adequate capital formation to provide for the costs of the future, the
costs of staying in business, the costs of "creative destruction"?
This alone makes Schumpeter's economic model the only one that can serve as the
starting point for the economic policies we need. Clearly the Keynesian - or classicist -
treatment of innovation as being "outside," and in fact peripheral to, the economy and
with minimum impact on it, can no longer be maintained (if it ever could have been). The
basic question of economic theory and economic policy, especially in highly developed
countries, is clearly: How can capital formation and productivity be maintained so that
rapid technological change as well as employment can be sustained? What is the
minimum profit needed to defray the costs of the future? What is the minimum profit
needed, above all, to maintain jobs and to create new ones?
Schumpeter gave no answer; he did not much believe in answers. But seventy years
ago, as a very young man, he asked what is clearly going to be the central question of
economic theory and economic policy in the years to come.
And then, during World War I, Schumpeter realized, long before anyone else - and a
good ten years before Keynes did - that economic reality was changing. He realized that
World War I had brought about the monetarization of the economies of all belligerents.
Country after country, including his own still fairly backward Austria-Hungary, had
succeeded during the war in mobilizing the entire liquid wealth of the community, partly
through taxation but mainly through borrowing. Money and credit, rather than goods and
services, had become the "real economy."
In a brilliant essay published in a German economic journal in July 1918 - when the
world Schumpeter had grown up in and had known was crashing down around his ears -
he argued that, from now on, money and credit would be the lever of control. What he
argued was that neither supply of goods, as the classicists had argued, nor demand for
goods, as some of the earlier dissenters had maintained, was going to be controlling
anymore. Monetary factors - deficits, money, credit, taxes - were going to be the
determinants of economic activity and of the allocation of resources.
This is, of course, the same insight on which Keynes later built his General Theory. But
Schumpeter's conclusions were radically different from those Keynes reached. Keynes
came to the conclusion that the emergence of the symbol economy of money and credit
made possible the "economist-king," the scientific economist, who by playing on a few
simple monetary keys - government spending, the interest rate, the volume of credit, or
the amount of money in circulation - would maintain permanent equilibrium with full
employment, prosperity, and stability. But Schumpeter's conclusion was that the
emergence of the symbol economy as the dominant economy opened the door to
tyranny, and, in fact, invited tyranny. That the economist now proclaimed himself
www.peterdrucker.at 5
infallible, he considered pure hubris. But, above all, he saw that it was not going to be
economists who would exercise the power, but politicians and generals.
And then, in the same year, just before World War I ended, Schumpeter published The
Tax State ("The Fiscal State" would be a better translation). Again, the insight is the
same Keynes reached fifteen years later (and, as he often acknowledged, thanks to
Schumpeter): the modern state, through the mechanisms of taxation and borrowing, has
acquired the power to shift inome and, through "transfer payments," to control the
distribution of the national product. To Keynes this power was a magic wand to achieve
both social justice and economic progress, and both economic stability and fiscal
responsibility. To Schumpeter - perhaps because he, unlike Keynes, was a student of
both Marx and history - this power was an invitation to political irresponsibilty, because it
eliminated al econimic safeguards against inflation. In the past the inability of the state
to tax more than a very small proportion of the gross national product, or to borrow
more than a very small part of the country's wealth, had made inflation self-limiting. Now
the only safeguard against inflation would be political, that is, self-discipline. And
Schumpeter was not very sanguine about the politician's capacity for self-descipline.
Schumpeter's work as an economist after World War I is of great importance to economic
theory. He became one of the fathers of business cycle theory.
But Schumpeter's real contribution during the thirty-two years between the end of World
War I and his death in 1950 was as a political economist. In 1942, when everyone was
scared of a worldwide deflationary depression, Schumpeter published his best-known
book, Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy, still, and deservedly, read widely. In this
book he argued that capitalism would be destroyed by its own success. This would breed
what we would now call the new class: bureaucrats, intellectuals, professors, lawyers,
journalists, all of them beneficiaries of capitalism's economic fruits and, in fact,
parasitical on them, and yet all of them opposed to the ethos of wealth production, of
saving, and of allocating resources to economic productivity. The forty years since this
book appeared have surely proved Schumpeter to be major prophet.
And then he proceeded to argue that capitalism would be destroyed by the very
democracy it had helped to create and made possible. For in a democracy, to be popular,
government would increasingly shift income from producer to nonproducer, would
increasingly move income from where it would be saved and become capital for
tomorrow to where it would be consumed. Government in a democracy would thus be
under increasing inflationary pressure. Eventually, he prophesied, inflation would destroy
both democracy and capitalism.
When he wrote this in 1942, almost everybody laughed. Nothing seemed less likely than
an inflation based on economic success. Now, forty years later, this has emerged as the
central problem of democracy and of a free-market economy alike, just as Schumpeter
had prophesied.
The Keynesian in the 1940s ushered in their "promised land," in which the economistking would guarantee the perfect equilibrium of an eternally stable economy through
control of money, credit, spending, and taxes. Schumpeter, however, increasingly
concerned himself with the question of how the public sector could be controlled and
limited so as to maintain political freedom and an economy capable of performance,
growth, and change. When death overtook him at his desk, he was revising the
presidential address he had given to the American Economic Association only a few days
earlier. The last sentence he wrote wa "The stagnationists are wrong in their diagnosis of
the reason the capitalist process should stagnate; they may still turn out to be right in
their prognosis that it will stagnate - with sufficient help from the public sector."
Keynes's best-known saying is surely "In the long run we are all dead." This is one of the
most fatuous remarks ever made. Of course, in the long run we are all dead. But Keynes
www.peterdrucker.at 6
in a wiser moment remarked that the deeds of today's politicians are usually based on
the theorems of long-dead econimists. And it is a total fallacy that, as Keynes implies,
optimizing the short term creates the right long-term future. Keynes is in large measure
responsible for the extreme short-term focus of modern politics, of modern economics,
and of modern business - the short-term focus that is now, with considerable justice,
considered a major weakness of American policymakers, both in government and in
business.
Schumpeter also knew that policies have to fit the short term. He learned this lesson the
hard way - as minister of finance in the newly formed Austrian republic in which he,
totally unsuccessfully, tried to stop inflation before it got out of hand. He knew that he
had failed because his measures were not acceptable in the short term - the very
measures that, two years later, a noneconomist, a politician and professor of moral
theology did apply to stop the inflation, but only after it had all but destroyed Austria's
economy and middle class.
But Schumpeter also knew that today's short-term measures have long-term impacts.
They irrevocably make the future. Not to think through the futurity of short-term
decisions and their impact long after "we are all dead" is irresponsible. It also leads to
the wrong decisions. It is this constant emphasis in Schumpeter on thinking through the
long-term consequences of the xpedient, the popular, the clever, and the brilliant that
makes him a great economist and the appropriate guide for today, when short-run,
clever, brilliant economics - and short-run, clever, brilliant politics - have become
bankrupt.
In some ways, Keynes and Schumpeter replayed the best-known confrontation of
philsophers in the Western tradition - the Platonic dialogue between Parmenides, the
brilliant, clever, irresistible sophist, and the slow-moving and ugly, but wise Socrates. No
one in the interwar years was more brilliant, more clever than Keynes. Schumpeter, by
contrast, appeared pedestrian - but he had wisdom. Cleverness carries the day. But
wisdom endureth.
VER MÁS AQUÍ