Un día, discutiendo acerca de la forma exacta de un elefante, no conseguían ponerse de acuerdo. Como ninguno de ellos había tocado nunca uno, decidieron salir al día siguiente a la busca de un ejemplar, y así salir de dudas.
ESCRIBA LO QUE DESEA LEER EN ESTE BLOG
jueves, 26 de enero de 2023
A Comparison of the Theories of Joseph Alois Schumpeter and John Maynard Keynes
A Comparison of the Theories of Joseph Alois Schumpeter and John Maynard Keynes
Aubrey Poon
Joseph Alois Schumpeter and John Maynard Keynes were the two greatest economists in the 21st century. They were incidentally born a few months apart, Schumpeter was born on February 8 1883 and Keynes was born on June 5 1883. They both contributed a monumental amount of work to economic theory, but their most famous masterpieces are, The General Theory of Employment, Interest and Money (by Keynes) and Theory of Economic Development and Business cycles (by Schumpeter). In these great works, both Schumpeter and Keynes conveyed problems with classical economics. Keynes, especially in the General Theory, explicitly attacks the classical framework, Schumpeter on the other hand, implicitly accepts it and uses it to explain his own models. Both Schumpeter and Keynes had different views on how capitalism works. Keynes, in respect to the General Theory, believed governmental actions are essential to sustain a capitalistic economy. Schumpeter, however, believed the fundamental impulse that sets and keeps a capitalist economy in motion comes from the introduction of so called new combination through innovation initiated by the entrepreneur (Schumpeter, 1942).
In essence, they were both intellectual opponents to each other but it was Schumpeter who explicitly attacked Keynes in his work. Schumpeter disagreed with Keynes’ assumption that techniques of production remain unchanged, he believed a changing production function is an essential process to capitalistic development (Smithies, 1951). But, Schumpeter‘s main charge against Keynes was that he was a strong advocator of government policies. Like most Austrian economist. Schumpeter disapproved government intervention because he believed it would impair capitalistic development (Smithies, 1951). Although the negative judgment that Schumpeter expressed about the General Theory testifies to the distance between the theories of Keynes and Schumpeter, they do have similarities in their works (Bertocco, 2006). In terms of monetary theory, they both share two common points of view. Firstly, in contrast to mainstream monetary theory, both Keynes and Schumpeter believed that the diffusion of money induces a radical modification into the way in which the economic system works (Bertocco, 2006). Secondly, both Keynes and Schumpeter justify why money and financial aggregates are not neutral, they both highlight the crucial role of the credit market and the banks; in contrast with mainstream monetary theories, who do not consider the credit market to crucial role in the economy (Bertocco, 2006).
In respect to the Theory of Economic Development, Schumpeter believed that the process of economic development was inherently dynamic, as opposed to the static structure of the theory of equilibrium, which is the central theme in classical theory (Velde, 2001). Schumpeter described the classical world, where supply always creates demand (Say Law), in term of a diagram called the circular flow (figure 1).
In this world, all goods would find a market and the behaviour of producers and consumers are merely routine (Velde, 2001), but Schumpeter does acknowledge that the production decisions are influenced by consumer’s preferences. Also, the economy would always tend to replicate itself unchangingly and even if the changes do occur, Schumpeter believed the factors that cause the change would not be enough to alter the structure of the economy (Bertocco, 2006). In essence, the economy is always at full employment. However, Schumpeter did not reject the classical theory of equilibrium explicitly as Keynes did, essentially he implicitly accepted and used it as a base to explain his own dynamic model (Velde, 2001). Therefore, the model of economic development is not a substitute for the classical theory of equilibrium but rather a necessary complement to it (Velde, 2001). Figure 1
Keynes, on the other hand, explicitly rejected the classical proposition. Firstly, Keynes denied the classical model in respect to saving and investment always being in equilibrium (Ekelund & Hebert, 1975). According to the classical model, the interest rate is always flexible and this means that any changes in investment or saving would never cause overproduction or underproduction in an economy (Ekelund & Hebert, 1975). However, to Keynes, saving and Sponsor investment were determined by a complex host of factors, such as the marginal propensity to consume and marginal efficiency of capital, in addition to the interest rate and also there was no guarantee that the two would necessarily be equal at a level of economic activity which produced full employment (Ekelund & Hebert, 1975).
But, what Keynes objected to most strongly in the classical reasoning was the notion that unemployment would disappear if workers would just accept a lower wage rate (Dillard, 1948). Keynes repudiated this classical assumption because he believed the rigidities in the economy, such as labour unions and minimum wage law, thwarts this classical fluid movement of wages and prices, which bring about an adjustment of the economy to full employment (Ekelund & Hebert, 1975). Also, he believed that labour behaviour was related to money wages, not the real wage. Therefore, labourer would refuse to take cuts in their money wage and this refusal, Keynes believed, was a direct denial of the classical wage rate adjustment mechanism (Ekelund & Hebert, 1975). To initiate economic development in a capitalist economy, Schumpeter believed that a disruption must occur in the static equilibrium world (circular flow). The main driver of the disruption, he believed, was the entrepreneur and the person who sponsors the entrepreneur, most commonly the bank (Velde, 2001). Therefore, the basic structure of Schumpeter’s model of economic development has two distinctive spheres, where on one hand it is static system that is either in equilibrium or striving for it (Velde, 2001), while, on the other hand, it is the symbiotic pair of the entrepreneur and the sponsor, who is always looking for ways to induce change in the peaceful yet boring routine life of the circular flow (Velde, 2001). Both spheres function within an endless reservoir of new combinations, but it is only the entrepreneur backed by the sponsor who is able to introduce new combinations and new routines in the circular flow (Velde, 2001). However, Schumpeter is realistic enough to see that the carrying out of new combinations involves more than an act of will, a command over means of production is necessary (Velde, 2001). Schumpeter argued that, innovations are carried out especially by new entrepreneurs, who do not own factor of production and he highlights the role of credit created by the banks as a key process to facilitate factor resources to them (Bertocco, 2006).
Keynes, however, unlike Schumpeter did not envisage a theory of capitalistic development. In essence, the General Theory is a theory of employment, Keynes believed that unemployment could still exist even if all the conditions necessary to restore perfectly free or thorough going competition among wage earners were to be realised (Dillard, 1948). He contended that the volume of employment is determined by effective demand, not by the wage bargains between workers and employers (Dillard, 1948). Demand to Keynes mean aggregate demand which is made up of consumption and investment (Dillard, 1948). The factor that affects consumption is the marginal propensity to consume, which is the proportion of income spent on consumption, while investment is determined by the marginal efficiency of capital, which is the expected return of new investment, and the interest rate (Dillard, 1948). Keynes normally assumed the marginal propensity to consume is relative stable and therefore, the level of employment is determined by the volume of investment (Dillard, 1948).
Keynes’ aggregate demand is very different to the traditional demand curve, which slants down toward the right, indicating that the quantity sold would increase as the price falls (Dillard, 1948). In his opinion, the aggregate demand (represented by DD in Figure 2) is upward sloping and it is a schedule of the proceeds expected from the sale of output resulting from varying amounts of employment (Dillard, 1948). In other words, as more labour is employed, more output is produced and the total proceeds are greater. Aggregate supply (represented by ZZ in Figure 2), on the other hand, closely resemble the traditional supply curve and to Keynes, it is a schedule that detail the minimum amounts of proceeds required to induce varying quantities of employment (Dillard, 1948). As the amount of proceeds increased, a greater amount of employment would be offered to workers by employers. But Keynes does not dwell into aggregate supply as much as aggregate demand. He normally assumed that aggregate supply is fixed. Figure 2
At point E in figure 2, aggregate demand intersects with aggregate supply and according to Keynes, the point of interaction determines the actual amount of employment at any time (Dillard, 1948). This is the crux of Keynes’ theory of employment. At this point, the entrepreneurs maximise their expected profits and if either more or less employment were offered, profits would be less (Dillard, 1948). Thus at any one time, there is, according to Keynes’ theory, a uniquely determined amount of employment which would be most profitable for entrepreneur to offer to works (Dillard, 1948). However, Keynes does state that, at this point it is not necessarily at full employment, for instance full employment may be at point B. There D1 D Z E $ N Employment P could be, Keynes concluded, an equilibrium level of income in an economy, but at less than full employment (Ekelund & Hebert, 1975).
In order to achieve this full employment point (point B figure 2), Keynes believed, investment demand must be equal to the gap between the aggregate supply price corresponding to full employment and the amount which consumers in the aggregate choose to spend for consumption out of income at full employment (Dillard, 1948). If an increased investment is equal to this gap, a multiplier effect would occur and drive the economy to a full employment point. Essentially this means, in order to have sufficient demand to sustain an increase in employment there must be an increase in real investment equal to the gap between income and consumption out that income (Dillard, 1948). In other words, employment cannot increase unless investment increases. However, according to Keynes, a typical investment demand would be inadequate to fill this gap and therefore, aggregate demand and aggregate supply intersects at a point less than full employment (Dillard, 1948). As a result, involuntarily unemployment arises and government actions, such as fiscal policy, Keynes believed, would relieve unemployment and underproduction in the economy (Ekelund & Hebert, 1975).
Both Schumpeter and Keynes were the most prominent economists in the 21th century and would have likely to come across each other works. Both had opposing view points but it was Schumpeter who explicitly attacked Keynes in his work. The first critique Schumpeter made in relation to Keynes’ General Theory was the unchanging production function that Keynes based his analysis on (Smithies, 1951). Schumpeter criticised the static structure of Keynes analysis based on the assumption of the existence of time invariant production functions, which allowed Keynes to convey the existence of a strict relationship between variation in production and in employment (Bertocco, 2006). Schumpeter believed that a static theory was wholly unsuitable to describe how a modern capitalist economy works (Bertocco, 2006) and he stated this disagreement in his review of the General Theory, “But disregarding this, reasoning on the assumption that variations in output are uniquely related to variations in employment imposes the further assumption that all production remain invariant. Now the outstanding feature of capitalism is that they do not but that, on the contrary, they are being incessantly revolutionized.” (Schumpeter, 1936)
In terms of unemployment, Schumpeter, especially in Business Cycles and the Theory of Economic Development, did not set forth a theory of employment, as Keynes did in his General Theory. Although it was probably not intended, Schumpeter did provide an explanation when unemployment would occur. His explanation of unemployment is totally different than Keynes’ explanation of unemployment and in essence, it is based on the changing production function (Bennion, 1943). He emphasized unemployment more importantly in his business cycles. Firstly, he states that a given level of unemployment could have occurred at the start of the upswing. This may be the result of monopoly or imperfect competition; some of it will be cyclical and inherited from the preceding cycle (Bennion, 1943). However, Schumpeter does state, once innovation has occurred and fueled the upswing, unemployment could still occur because the emergence of innovation (Creative Destruction) can spell ‘economic death’ to other firms (Bennion, 1943). Also, Schumpeter does not guarantee that other firms would instantly reemploy these factors of production, which has become unemployed due to creative destruction (Bennion, 1943). Ultimately, temporary saturation of certain market sets in and it becomes increasing difficult to plan new things and the risk of failure increases greatly. Hence a recession occurs and it is during this period, Schumpeter believed that the emergence of unemployment steadily increases (Bennion, 1943). The high level of liquidation of businesses eventually forces the economy below the equilibrium and into the depression phase. It is the depression phase, Schumpeter believed that unemployment would feed upon itself and he states “Each addition to unemployment will cause further and further unemployment” (Bennion, 1943)
The main objection Schumpeter had over Keynes works, was that he was a strong advocator of governmental policy (Smithies, 1951). Like most Austrian economists, Schumpeter disapproved of government intervention because it impairs capitalistic behaviour (Smithies, 1951). Both Schumpeter and Keynes were brought up with different influences and this was the main reason why Schumpeter has so such much hostility to Keynes work (Smithies, 1951). Keynes was a lineal descendant of the English Utilitarian and Schumpeter was not. Thus, Smithies 1951 states “Keynes regarded worth while theory as a basis for program of action. Schumpeter theory led him to look with foreboding upon action to which such theories and programs might lead” With his Utilitarian views, Keynes believed that both distribution of income and the level of effective demand should be control by the state (government) (Smithies, 1951). But Schumpeter could not comprehend this, his view was that if production and distribution were exposed to government actions, anti-capitalistic program such as high progressive taxation or heavy death duties would occur (Smithies, 1951).
In addition, Keynes’ General Theory is based on the short run and it encourages governments to take a short run point of view (Smithies, 1951). In essence, his views were that if the government looks after the short run, the long run would after itself. Again, Schumpeter believed this idol of Keynes, promotes anti-capitalistic behaviour. Even if governments short run policies were based on some notion of the common good rather than on the flow of the political tides, Schumpeter believed, it would still be anti-capitalistic (Smithies, 1951). Also, Schumpeter believed, the rich entrepreneur profit that is essential to capitalistic success does not conform to Utilitarian standards of equity in the short run (Smithies, 1951). However, Schumpeter main charge against Keynes was not that he pursued governmental actions for the common good, but that he made it intellectually respectable that these action, which Schumpeter saw as anti-capitalistic, could work in the economy (Smithies, 1951). In essence, he tore down the barriers, imposed by the classical economics and the Benthamite tradition, that had restrained the advocates of intervention in the past and had provided effective intellectual opposition to it(Smithies, 1951).
In Schumpeter words, Keynes destroyed “The last pillar of the bourgeois argument and made it possible for his followers to justify almost any policy provided it increased the propensity to consume.”(Schumpeter, 1946) Although both Schumpeter and Keynes great works are primarily concerned with two different things, they do have similarities on how the economy works. In terms of monetary theory, both share two common points of views, and Schumpeter acknowledges Keynes’ work in money, in his review of the General Theory he states “I wish however to welcome his purely monetary theory of interest, which is, as far as I can see, the first to follow upon my own” (Schumpeter, 1936) Firstly, both Schumpeter and Keynes share a common viewpoint that the diffusion of money radically changes the structure of the economy (Bertocco, 2006). Keynes maintains this point by distinguishing between a real exchange economy and a monetary economy. In a real exchange economy, Keynes believed money is just an instrument that makes it possible to reduce the costs of the exchange (Bertocco, 2006). In a monetary economy, however, fluctuation in money can induce changes to the economic system (Bertocco, 2006). Schumpeter, on the other hand, like Keynes, maintains this point by also distinguishing between a pure exchange economy and a capitalist economy. The pure exchange economy is essentially the classical economy, where money is only an instrument to facilitate trade, which is obtained in exchange for goods or services (Bertocco, 2006). In capitalist economy it includes the entrepreneur and the sponsor (bank) in addition to a pure exchange economy, where money is created by the banks to initiate economic development (Bertocco, 2006). Secondly, both Keynes and Schumpeter justify that money is not neutral, they both highlight the importance of the credit market and the banks in the economy (Bertocco, 2006). They both use different arguments to support this claims, Keynes for example, uses the term monetary economy which refers to an economy in which Say’s Law does not apply to justify that money is not neutral (Bertocco, 2006). He believed in this economy the level of income is subject to fluctuations that depend on oscillations in aggregate demand (Bertocco, 2006). In turn, these fluctuations are made possible by the presence of money and Keynes explicitly states “the fluctuations in effective demand can be properly described as a monetary phenomenon” (Keynes, 1933B) Schumpeter, on the other hand, highlights the creation of credit as a key role in the process of economic development (Bertocco, 2006). He argues that credit becomes a necessary factor for development because innovations are made by new entrepreneurs who do not own means of production (Bertocco, 2006). Therefore, the creations of credit by the banks supply the innovators–entrepreneurs with the purchasing power necessary to divert the resources to them.
In conclusion, both Schumpeter’s and Keynes’ famous masterpiece contained problems with classical economics. Keynes explicitly attacks the classical framework (Dillard, 1948), Schumpeter on the other hand implicitly accepts it and uses it as a base to explain his own dynamic model (Velde, 2001). They both share two different views on how capitalism operates, Keynes believed government policies are essential to sustain a capitalistic economy (Dillard, 1948). Schumpeter, however, believed that the process of capitalistic development is initiated by the introduction of new combination through innovation created by the entrepreneur, backed by the sponsor (Velde, 2001). Essentially, both of them were intellectual opponents but it was Schumpeter who explicitly attacked Keynes directly in his work. Schumpeter disagreed with unchanging production function that Keynes’ based his analysis on in the General Theory (Smithies, 1951). Schumpeter believed a changing production function is essential to capitalistic development. In the General Theory, Keynes strongly advocates for government policies and Schumpeter, like most Austrian economist, disagrees with this assumption. He believed any form of government intervention would impair capitalistic behaviour (Smithies, 1951). Although both Schumpeter and Keynes theories are primarily concerned with two different things, they do have similarities in their work. In terms of monetary theory, they both share two common points of view. First, in contrast to mainstream theory, both state that the diffusion of money induces a radical modification into the way in which an economy works (Bertocco, 2006). Secondly, they both describe reasons why money and financial aggregates are not neutral, they highlight the crucial role of the credit market and the banks (Bertocco, 2006).
Schumpeter And Keynes
Schumpeter And Keynes
THE TWO GREATEST economists of this century, Joseph A. Schumpeter and John Maynard Keynes, were born, only a few months apart, a hundred years ago: Schumpeter on Feb. 8, 1883 in a provincial Austrian town, Keynes on June 5, 1883 in Cambridge, England. (And they died only four years apart -- Schumpeter in Connecticut on Jan. 8, 1950, Keynes in southern England on Apr. 21, 1946.) The centenary of Keynes' birth is being celebrated with a host of books, articles, conferences and speeches. If the centenary of Schumpeter's birth were noticed at all, it would be in a small doctoral seminar. And yet it is becoming increasingly clear that it is Schumpeter who will shape the thinking and inform the questions on economic theory and economic policy for the rest of this century, if not for the next 30 or 50 years.
THE TWO MEN WERE NOT ANTAGONISTS. Both challenged long-standing assumptions. The opponents of Keynes were the very "Austrians" Schumpeter himself had broken away from as a student, the neoclassical economists of the Austrian School. And while Schumpeter considered all of Keynes' answers wrong, or at least misleading, he was a sympathetic critic. Indeed, it was Schumpeter who established Keynes in America. When Keynes' General Theory came out, Schumpeter, by then the senior member of the Harvard economics faculty, told his students to read the book and told them also that Keynes' work had totally superseded his own earlier writings on money.
Keynes, in turn, considered Schumpeter one of the few contemporary economists worthy of his respect. In his lectures he again and again referred to the works Schumpeter had published during World War I, and especially to Schumpeter's essay on the Rechenpfennige (i.e., money of account) as the initial stimulus for his own thoughts on money. Keynes' most successful policy initiative, the proposal that Britain and the U.S. finance World War II by taxes rather than by borrowing, came directly out of Schumpeter's 1918 warning of the disastrous consequences of the debt financing of World War I.
Schumpeter and Keynes are often contrasted politically, with Schumpeter being portrayed as the "conservative" and Keynes as the "radical." The opposite is more nearly. right. Politically Keynes' views were quite similar to what we now call" neoconservative." His theory had its origins in his passionate attachment to the free market and in his desire to keep politicians and governments out of it. Schumpeter, by contrast, had serious doubts about the free market. He thought that an "intelligent monopoly" -- the American Bell Telephone system, for instance -- had a great deal to recommend itself. It could afford to take the long view instead of being driven from transaction to transaction by short-term expediency. His closest friend for many years was the most radical and most doctrinaire of Europe's left-wing socialists, the Austrian Otto Bauer, who, though staunchly anticommunist, was even more anticapitalist. And Schumpeter, while never even close to being a socialist himself, served during 1919 as minister of finance in Austria's only socialist government between the wars. Schumpeter always maintained that Marx had been dead wrong in every one of his answers. But he still considered himself a son of Marx and held him in greater esteem than any other economist. At least, so he argued, Marx asked the right questions -- and to Schumpeter questions were always more important than answers.
The differences between Schumpeter and Keynes go much deeper than economic theorems or political views. The two saw a different economic reality, were concerned with different problems and defined "economics" quite differently. These differences are highly important to an understanding of today's economic world.
Keynes, for all that he broke with classical economics, operated entirely within its framework. He was a "heretic" rather than an "infidel." Economics, for Keynes, was the equilibrium economics of Ricardo's 1810 theories, which dominated the 19th century. This economics deals with a closed system and a static one. Keynes' key question was the same question the 19th-century economists had asked: "How can one maintain an economy in balance and stasis?"
For Keynes, the main problems of economics are the relationship between the "real economy" of goods and services and the "symbol economy" of money and credit; the relationship between individuals and businesses and the "macro-economy" of the nation-state; and finally, whether production (that is, supply) or consumption (that is, demand) provides the driving force of the economy. In this sense Keynes was in a direct line with Ricardo, John Stuart Mill, the "Austrians" and Alfred Marshall. However much they differed otherwise, most of these 19th-century economists, and that includes Marx, had given the same answers to these questions: The "real economy" controls, and money is only the "veil of things"; the micro-economy of individuals and businesses determines, and government can, at best, correct minor discrepancies and, at worst, create dislocations; and supply controls, with demand a function of it.
KEYNES ASKED the same questions that Ricardo, Mill, Marx, the "Austrians" and Marshall had asked but, with unprecedented audacity, turned every one of the answers upside down. In the Keynesian system, money and credit are "real," and goods and services dependent on, and shadows of, the "symbol economy"; the macro-economy, the economy of the nation-state, is everything, with individuals and firms having neither power to influence, let alone to direct, the economy nor the ability to make effective decisions counter to the forces of the "macro-economy"; and economic phenomena, capital formation, productivity and employment are functions of demand.
By now we know, as Schumpeter knew 50 years ago, that every one of these Keynesian answers is the wrong answer. At least they are valid only for special cases and within fairly narrow ranges. Take, for instance, Keynes' key theorem: that monetary events -- government deficits, interest rates, credit volume and volume of money in circulation -- determine demand and with it economic conditions. This assumes -- as Keynes himself stressed -- that the turnover velocity of money is constant and not capable of being changed over the short term by individuals or firms. Schumpeter pointed out 50 years ago that all evidence negates this assumption. And indeed, whenever tried, Keynesian economic policies, whether in the original Keynesian or in the modified Friedman version, have been defeated by the "micro-economy" of businesses and individuals, unpredictably and without warning, changing the turnover velocity of money almost overnight.
WHEN THE KEYNESIAN PRESCRIPTIONS were initially tried -- in the U.S. in the early New Deal days -- they seemed at first to work. But then, around 1935 or so, consumers and businesses suddenly sharply reduced the turnover velocity of money with-in a few short months, which aborted a recovery based on government deficit spending and brought about a second collapse of the stock market in 1937. The best example, however, is what happened in this country in the last few years. The Federal Reserve's purposeful attempt to control the economy by controlling money supply has largely been defeated by consumers and businesses who suddenly and almost violently shifted deposits from thrifts into money market funds and from long-term investments into liquid assets -- that is, from low-velocity into high-velocity money -- to the point where no one can really tell any more what the "money supply" is or ever what the term means. Individuals and businesses seeking to optimize their self-interest and guided by their perception of economic reality will always find a way to beat the "system" -- whether, as in the Soviet bloc, through converting the entire economy into one gigantic black market or, as in the U.S. in the last few years, through transforming the financial system overnight despite laws, regulations or economists.
This does not mean that economics is likely to return to pre-Keynesian neoclassicism. Keynes' critique of the neoclassic answers is as definitive as Schumpeter's critique of Keynes. But because we now that individuals can and will defeat the system, we have lost the certainty that Keynes imposed on economics and that has made the Keynesian system the lodestar of economic theory and economic policy for 50 years. Both Friedman's monetarism and supply-side economics are desperate attempts to patch up the Keynesian system of equilibrium economics. But it is unlikely that either can restore the self-contained, self-confident equilibrium economics, let alone an economic theory or an economic policy in which one factor, whether government spending, interest rates, money supply or tax cuts, controls the economy predictably and with near-certainty.
That the Keynesian answers were not going to prove any more valid than the pre-Keynesian ones that they replaced was clear to Schumpeter from the beginning. But to him this was much less important than that the Keynesian questions -- the questions of Keynes' predecessors as well -- were not, Schumpeter thought, the important questions at all. To him the basic fallacy was the very assumption with which Keynes had started out: the assumption that the healthy, the "normal," economy is an economy in static equilibrium. Schumpeter, from his student days on, held that a modern economy is always in dynamic disequilibrium. Schumpeter's economy is not a closed system like Newton's universe -- or Keynes' "macro-economy." It is forever growing and changing, and is biological rather than mechanistic in nature. If Keynes was a "heretic," Schumpeter was an "infidel."
Schumpeter was himself a student of the great men of Austrian economics and at a time when Vienna was the world capital of economic theory. He held his teachers in lifelong affection. But his doctoral dissertation -- it became the earliest of his great books, The Theory of Economic Development (which in its original German version came out in 1911, when Schumpeter was only 28 years old) -- starts out with the assertion that the central problem of economics is not equilibrium but structural change. This then led to Schumpeter's famous theorem of the innovator as the true subject of economics.
CLASSICAL ECONOMICS considered innovation to be outside the system, as Keynes did, too. Innovation belonged in the category of "outside catastrophes" like earthquakes, climate or war, which, everybody knew, have profound influence on the economy but are not part of economics. Schumpeter insisted that, on the contrary, innovation -- that is, entrepreneurship that moves resources from old and obsolescent to new and more productive employments -- is the very essence of economics and most certainly of a modern economy.
He derived this notion, as he was the first to admit, from Marx. But he used it to disprove Marx. Schumpeter's Economic Development does what neither the classical economists nor Marx nor Keynes was able to do: It makes profit fulfill an economic function. In the economy of change and innovation, profit, in contrast to Marx, is not a Mehrwert, a "surplus value" stolen from the workers. On the contrary, it is the only source of jobs for workers and of labor income. The theory of economic development shows that no one except the innovator makes a genuine "profit," and the innovator's profit is always quite short-lived. But innovation in Schumpeter's famous phrase is also "creative destruction." It makes obsolete yesterday's capital equipment and capital investment. The more an economy progresses, the more capital formation will it therefore need. Thus what the classical economist -- or the accountant or the stock exchange -- considers "profit" is a genuine cost, the cost of staying in business, the cost of a future in which nothing is predictable except that today's profitable business will become tomorrow's white elephant. Thus, capital formation and productivity are needed to maintain the wealth-producing capacity of the economy and, above all, to maintain today's jobs and to create tomorrow's jobs.
SCHUMPETER'S "INNOVATOR" with his "creative destruction" is the only theory so far to explain why there is something we call "profit." The classical economists very well knew that their theory did not give any rationale for profit. Indeed, in the equilibrium economics of a closed economic system there is no place for profit, no justification for it, no explanation of it. If profit is, however, a genuine cost, and especially if profit is the only way to maintain jobs and to create new ones, then "capitalism" becomes again a moral system.
Morality and profits. The classical economists had pointed out that profit is needed as the incentive for the risk taker. But is this not a bribe and thus impossible to justify morally? This dilemma had driven the most brilliant of 19th-century economists, John Stuart Mill, to embrace socialism in his later years. It had made it easy for Marx to fuse dispassionate analysis of the "system" with the moral revulsion of an Old Testament prophet against the "exploiters." The weakness on moral grounds of the profit incentive enabled Marx at once to condemn the "capitalist" as wicked and immoral, and assert "scientifically" that he serves no function and that his speedy demise is "inevitable." As soon, however, as one shifts from the axiom of an unchanging, self-contained, closed economy to Schumpeter's dynamic, growing, moving, changing economy, what is called "profit" is no longer immoral. It becomes a moral imperative. Indeed, the question then is no longer the question that agitated the classicists and still agitated Keynes: How can the economy be structured to minimize the bribe of the functionless surplus called "profit" that has to be handed over to the "capitalist" to keep the economy going? The question in Schumpeter's economics is always: Is there sufficient profit? Is there adequate capital formation to provide for the costs of the future, the costs of staying in business, the costs of "creative destruction"?
THIS ALONE makes Schumpeter's economic model the only one that can serve as the starting point for the economic policies we need. Clearly the Keynesian -- or classicist -- treatment of innovation as being "outside" and in fact peripheral to the economy and with minimum impact on it, can no longer be maintained (if it ever could be). The basic question of economic theory and economic policy, especially in highly developed countries, is clearly: How can capital formation and productivity be maintained so that rapid technological change as well as employment can be sustained? What is the minimum profit needed to defray the costs of the future? What is the minimum profit needed, above all, to maintain jobs and to create new ones?
Schumpeter gave no answer -- he did not much believe in answers. But 70 years ago, as a very young man, he asked what is clearly going to be the central question of economic theory and economic policy in the years to come.
And then, during World War I, Schumpeter realized, long before anyone else -- and a good ten years before Keynes did -- that economic reality was changing. He realized that World War I had brought about the monetarization of the economies of all belligerents. Country after country, including his own still fairly backward Austria-Hungary, had succeeded during the war in mobilizing the entire liquid wealth of the community, partly through taxation, but mainly through borrowing. Money and credit, rather than goods and services, had become the "real economy."
In a brilliant essay published in a German economic journal in July 1918 -- when the world Schumpeter had grwon up in and had known was crashing down around his ears -- he argued that, from now on, money and credit would be the lever of control. What he argued was that neither supply of goods, as the classicists had argued, nor demand for goods, as some of the earlier dissenters had maintained, was going to be controlling anymore. Monetary factors -- deficits, money, credit, taxes -- were going to be the determinants of economic activity and of the allocation of resources.
This is, of course, the same insight on which Keynes later built his General Theory. But Schumpeter's conclusions were radically different from those Keynes reached. Keynes came to the conclusion that the emergence of the "symbol economy" of money and credit made possible the "economist-king," the scientific economist, who, by playing on a few simple monetary keys -- government spending, the interest rate, the volume of credit or the amount of money in circulation -- would maintain permanent equilibrium with full employment, prosperity and stability. But Schumpeter's conclusion was that the emergence of the "symbol economy" as the dominant economy opened the door to tyranny and, in fact, invited tyranny. That the economist now proclaimed himself infallible, he considered pure hubris. But, above all, he saw that it was not going to economists who would exercise the power, but politicians and generals.
And then, in the same year, just before World War I ended, Schumpeter published The Tax State ("The Fiscal State" would be a better translation). Again, the insight is the same Keynes reached 15 years later (and, as he often acknowledged, thanks to Schumpeter): The modern state, through the mechanisms of taxation and borrowing, has acquired the power to shift income and, through "transfer payments," to control the distribution of the national product. To Keynes this power was a magic wand to achieve both social justice and economic progress, and both economic stability and fiscal responsibility. To Schumpeter -- perhaps because he, unlike Keynes, was a student of both Marx and history -- this power was an invitation to political irresponsibility, because it eliminated all economic safeguards against inflation. In the past the inability of the state to tax more than a very small proportion of the gross national product, or to borrow more than a very small part of the country's wealth, had made inflation self-limiting. Now the only safeguard against inflation would be political, that is, self-discipline. And Schumpeter was not very sanguine about the politician's capacity for self-discipline.
Schumpeter's work as an economist after World War I is of great importance to economic theory. He became one of the fathers of business cycle theory.
BUT SCHUMPETER'S REAL contribution during the 32 years between the end of World War I and his death in 1950 was as a political economist. In 1942, when everyone was scared of a World-wide deflationary depression, Schumpeter published his best-known book, Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy, still, and deservedly, read widely. In this book he argued that capitalism would be destroyed by its own success. This would breed what we would now call the "new class": bureaucrats, intellectuals, professors, lawyers, journalists, all of them beneficiaries of capitalism's economic fruits and, in fact, parasitical on them, and yet all of them opposed to the ethos of wealth production, of saving and of allocating resources to economic productivity. The 40 years since this book appeared have surely proved Schumpeter to be a major prophet.
And then he proceeded to argue that capitalism would be destroyed by the very democracy it had helped create and made possible. For in a democracy, to be popular, government would increasingly become the "tax state," would increasingly shift income from producer to non-producer, would increasingly move income from where it would be saved and become capital for tomorrow to where it would be consumed. Government in a democracy would thus be under increasing inflationary pressure. Eventually, he prophesied, inflation would destroy both democracy and capitalism.
When he wrote this in 1942, almost everybody laughed. Nothing seemed less likely than an inflation based on economic success. Now 40 years later, this has emerged as the central problem of democracy and of a free-market economy alike, just as Schumpeter had prophesied.
The Keynesians in the Forties ushered in their "promised land," in which the economist-king would guarantee the perfect equilibrium of an eternally stable economy through control of money, credit, spending and taxes. Schumpeter, however, increasingly concerned himself with the question of how the public sector could be controlled and limited so as to maintain political freedom and an economy capable of performance, growth and change. When death overtook him at his desk, he was revising the presidential address he had given to the American Economic Association only a few days earlier. The last sentence he wrote was: "The stagnationists are wrong in their diagnosis of the reason the capitalist process should stagnate; they may still turn out to be right in their prognosis that it will stagnate -- with sufficient help from the public sector."
Keynes' best-known saying is surely, "In the long run we are all dead." This is one of the most fatuous remarks ever made. Of course, in the long run we are all dead. But Keynes in a wiser moment remarked that the deeds of today's politicians are usually based on the theorems of long-dead economists. And it is a total fallacy that, as Keynes implies, optimizing the short term creates the right long-term future. Keynes is in large measure responsible for the extreme short-term focus of modern politics, of modern economics and modern business -- the short-term focus that is now, with considerable justice, considered a major weakness of American policymakers, both in government and in business.
SCHUMPETER ALSO KNEW that policies have to fit the short term. He learned this lesson the hard way -- as minister of finance in the newly formed Austrian republic in which he, totally unsuccessful, tried to stop inflation before it got out of hand. He knew that he had failed because his measures were not acceptable in the short term -- the very measures that, two years later, a non-economist, a politician and professor of moral theology did apply to stop the inflation, but only after it had all but destroyed Austria's economy and middle class.
But Schumpeter also knew that today's short-term measures have long-term impacts. They irrevocably make the future. Not to think through the futurity of short-term decisions and their impact long after "we are all dead" is irresponsible. It also leads to the wrong decisions. It is this constant emphasis in Schumpeter on thinking through the long-term consequences of the expedient, the popular, the clever and the brilliant, that makes him a great economist and the appropriate guide for today, when short-run, clever, brilliant economics -- and short-run, clever, brilliant politics -- have become bankrupt.
In some ways, Keynes and Schumpeter replayed the best-known confrontation of philosophers in the Western tradition -- the Platonic dialog between Parmenides, the brilliant, clever, irresistible sophist, and the slow-moving and ugly, but wise, Socrates. No one in the interwar years was more brilliant, more clever than Keynes. Schumpeter, by contrast, appeared pedestrian -- but he had wisdom. Cleverness carries the day. But wisdom endureth